Possibility lies unseen in the
fabric of reality. It is possibility, and nothing more than that, which may, in
fact, be the fabric of reality. Possible Universes, possible
histories, possible phenomena, and possible resolutions of every kind “wait”
within it. At every juncture where a decision is being made, at every point
where there is a choice of futures, in every situation where a variable is at
work, at every place where chains of consequence are intersecting, at every
interval where uncertainty is about to be resolved, one of the most powerful
and pervasive features of possibility is about to come into play: randomness. Many researchers and
observers have come to the conclusion that randomness—the presence, in any
given dynamic situation, of variables that will have non-predictable effects on
the situation—is a ubiquitous feature of reality. (The word stochastic is sometimes used as a
synonym for random.) Randomness is studied in large part through the
mathematics of probability, which
many people call chance. And
randomness appears to be one of the “masters” of both the Universe itself and
the human life which has emerged within it. It is a constant factor in the
events, great and small, that comprise a human life.
These events often seem to occur
out of nowhere. Seemingly impossible or unlikely things (such as a meteorite
crashing into a house) actually happen. Good “luck” or bad “luck” just seems to
follow some people. People sometimes hit it big in games of chance. Seemingly
hopeless situations can unexpectedly resolve themselves in a way favorable to
those involved in them. People’s lives are altered by chance introductions to
other people. Individuals run into people they once knew and never imagined
they would see again. Tragedies strike with brutal suddenness. And the story of
life often seems incomprehensible at times, even senseless, littered as it is
with the unexpected and the inexplicable.
To make sense of this apparent
capriciousness, most humans seem to need an explanation
of some sort for the events that engulf them, and for the way in which the
world seems to work. A great many of these humans believe that all events have
been foreordained. This belief is sometimes called a belief in Fate. Sometimes
it’s called a belief in Predestination or Determinism. But the terms all mean
the same thing: events happen in a certain way because they were meant to, and there was no other way
they could have happened. Most humans
are loath to believe that it might be otherwise. To suggest that randomness is
at work in life often elicits responses ranging from despair to outright
hostility. Many humans hate randomness because they want there to be a why. Especially when things are at their
worst, the only comfort many humans can take is the conviction that “all is, or
will be, for the best”. To invoke the apparently arbitrary element of chance
into the situation is to say there is no why. And for many, such a
conclusion is intolerable. For many people, the future needs to be predictable,
at least in the general sense. If it isn’t, the implications can be terrifying
for them.
Many humans are fearful of
randomness because it robs them of their sense of being in control of things.
Even worse, the existence of randomness robs them of the hope that some Higher
Power (a god, Karma, ancestral spirits, and so on) is guiding life and has an
Ultimate Purpose in mind for everything, a great Plan that will ultimately
“balance the Universe” and make everything come out all right, however “all
right” might be understood. They cling to the idea of predestination or fate
because they desperately want to believe someone
or something has matters under
control, especially when the brutality and chaos of life are all too evident
and all too near. (The belief in fate can be so all-encompassing that it erases
the sense of personal responsibility; after all, if it was fated, an individual
might say, “there was nothing I could have done anyway, so it’s just as well
that I didn’t do anything.”) But there seems to be no getting around it:
randomness is evidently real, and it would appear to be pervasive in the true
sense, permeating the physical world, and upending all human expectations.
It is natural to ask a crucially
important question: Is quantum
indeterminacy the origin of randomness on the macroscopic level? The answer
appears to be: in rare circumstances it can be, but since the behavior of
subatomic particles is predictable at the group
level, the structure and function of the macroscopic world seem to be generally
consistent. Yet, given the Many Worlds hypothesis, it could be argued that on
the broadest scale reality is being shaped by chance occurrences, namely, the
random observation of an event which leads to the creation of an alternate
history.
My own (amateur’s) hypothesis is
that the classically-governed macroscopic world is composed of elements that
behave in a quantum manner, but these quantum elements decohere in such a way
that the consistency of the classical world is maintained. In other words, the
uncertainty in the physical world is resolved in such a way, and at a “low”
enough level, that it is not noticeable to humans. For example, it’s not how the beam of light goes from point A
to point B, testing every possibility, it’s that it does go from point A to point B in a predictable manner.
Randomness, therefore, chiefly lies in the classical domain. It is governed by
the addition or multiplication of probabilities, combined with a sequence of
“decisions”, many of them unconscious, that lead to definable outcomes. The one
realm where quantum indeterminacy may play a role in randomness is,
interestingly, the function of the human brain. Consciousness may have quantum
elements because the neurotransmitters and neural structures upon which it is
based may operate according to quantum rules.
I am not concerned here, by the
way, with the mathematical quest to determine what a truly random number sequence
is. I am concerned with randomness as it is found in ordinary human life, and,
consequently, in the course of human history. In that course, as far as I can
determine, every event is the inheritor, the descendent of so many other
events, that tracing the line of causation quickly becomes impossible. When
these events touch directly on the lives of conscious beings, these beings make
a response of some sort to them—even if the response is to do nothing. Every
event is the outcome of a series of yes/no, black/white, utterly binary
“choices” that, laid on top of one another, yield a result that can only be called randomness. A thousand
choices up a chain of events a simple decision was made—will we go this way or
that way? From that choice sprouted innumerable others, each adding an
unexpected turn. The sum total of those simple choices is the complex set of
variables that produce the human perception of randomness.
Probability
Randomness is based on
probability, or more accurately, a series of probabilities unfolding and
manifesting themselves through time. Probability involves the sum total of
things that can happen in a given
situation—the situation’s universe of
possibilities, or its sample space—
and the frequency with which these possibilities actually occur. An event
occurs because a whole sequence of probabilities played themselves out in the
events that led up to it. In areas open to human study, probability estimates
are the product of human record keeping, which is by no means infallible, of course.
Leonard Mlodinow, in his
wonderful popular work The Drunkard’s
Walk, explains the basic rules that govern probability. He summarizes them
this way:
1. The probability that two events will both occur can never be greater
than the probability that each will occur individually.1
2. If two
possible events, A and B, are independent, then the probability that both A and
B will occur is equal to the product of their individual probabilities. For
example, if in the life of a person there is an event that has a probability of
1 in 50 over the course of a year and an event that has a probability of 1 in
5,000 over the course of a year, if they are truly independent events, the odds
that both will happen to the same person in the same year is 1/50
x 1/5,000, which is 1/250,000. 2
3. If an
event can have a number of different and distinct possible outcomes, A, B, C,
and so on, then the probability that either A or B will occur is equal to the
sum of the individual probabilities of A and B, and the sum of the
probabilities of all the possible outcomes (A, B, C, and so on) is 1 (that is,
100 percent.) In other words, as
Mlodinow explains, when you want to know the chances that two independent
events will occur, you multiply; if you want to know the chances of either of
two mutually exclusive events occurring,
you add.3 If there is a 20% chance of person A appearing somewhere
(a party, for example), a 25% chance of person B appearing at the same place,
and a 30% chance of person C showing up, there is a 75% chance that someone from the set ABC will show up at
the appointed spot. (The odds of all three showing up, however, would be only
1.5%.) Of course, as one of my mathematically-gifted friends has pointed out,
in real life the odds wouldn’t necessarily add up or multiply that cleanly. A,
B, and C might know each other, for example, and that might play into their
decision to attend or not attend. There are conditional
probability equations that are used to calculate real-life probabilities
more scientifically.
The need to calculate these
real-life probabilities has spawned a sophisticated subspecialty within
mathematics, and the problems it deals with reveal to us the full complexity of
the probability that weaves through our lives. Mathematicians working in probability
theory are attempting to put into a rigorous form the work of the first people
who studied the nature of chance, many of whom wrote about such matters as odds
in card games and dice throws. The chief issues in probability theory include
such matters as assessing what a truly independent event is, the definition and
classification of random variables, determining the independence of random
variables, the properties of expectation (which deals with a great many
repetitions of a given phenomenon), situations containing an infinite number of
variables, and Markov chains, which deal with probabilities of transitions from
one state (status) to another in a finite universe of possibilities, among
others. (The mathematics of these subjects I leave to those more gifted than I.)4
In any situation in which
multiple outcomes are possible, we need to determine how many possible outcomes actually exist. For example, in a coin
toss where the coin is allowed to land on the ground, the coin can either be
heads or tails (assuming that it will never land on its side). No other
outcomes are possible, so the universe of coin-flip possibilities is extremely
small and well-delineated. But what of other situations? Let’s say we have an
individual who has the financial means to travel to any part of the world he or
she desires. This person is going to make a decision about his or her travel
plans. How many possible outcomes are in that universe? Moreover, how many
variables are at play in the actual making of the decision?
Or let’s consider a businessman
who has to travel extensively during the course of a year, meeting potential
clients, and sometimes winning the business of the people he meets. In that
universe of possibilities there are: A. The number of stops the businessman
makes in a year. B. The number of people he will encounter at those stops C.
The varying emotional and intellectual receptiveness of the people he meets. D.
His ability to communicate effectively with his potential clients, an ability
which will be determined by such factors as his mental acuity on a given day
and his relative physical health. E. The number of new clients he actually wins
during the year. How many possible outcomes are in that universe, and how many
of those outcomes rest on factors which cannot be predicted in advance? (And
this isn’t even taking into consideration all the possible combinations of
sales/non-sales on the part of the salesman.) The success rates of salespeople
can be calculated, but predicting the success of any salesperson in any given
year is a highly uncertain enterprise. And this situation represents an
extremely small part of the sum of the human experience over the course of a
single year.
The “bigger” and more complex an
event is, the greater the probability of the unexpected occurring. When an
event involves a great many humans doing a great many things over a large
enough area over a long enough time, the odds are very, very good that some
random events will occur, including those which can alter the ultimate outcome
of the main event. These odds are good because the universe of possible
outcomes is so huge in a “big” event. In a war the size of the Second World
War, even if one could predict the probability of either an Allied or Axis
victory, a seemingly straightforward binary choice, the universe of
possibilities was of such enormity that no one could have conceivably predicted
the detailed course of the war, or
the specific features of its outcome.
There was no possible way that anyone could have foreseen the individual events
of which the war was comprised, nor could they have known the outcome of
specific human actions in advance. Human will had less to do with the outcome
of the struggle than we might suppose.
Various areas of the Earth are
governed by local probabilities. When people from these areas come into contact
with those of other regions who have been shaped by different distributions of
probabilities, the effects can be particularly unpredictable. Differences in
the geographic settings of different cultures are a major source of these
variable probabilities. Some people have been conditioned by harsh terrains or
brutal climates. Others have faced more temperate conditions and far different
challenges. Cultures with high population densities and heavy rates of
interpersonal interaction will have different probability sets than cultures
where human interaction is minimal. The point is, the action of probability is
not uniform over the surface of the Earth or throughout all human populations.
In the sparsely populated regions of the world the randomness of life tends to
come from the natural elements that have caused the region to be thinly
populated to begin with. In more populous regions, probabilities stemming from
the actions of others might play a more dominant role. And it is by no means a
certainty that people in sparsely populated regions are more at risk than those
from heavily populated areas. In many ways, the greatest threat to a human is
other humans.
Sources of Randomness in Human Life
So randomness, the expression of
the probabilities that lie all around us, is the great unknown variable of
existence. The sources of randomness in the human experience are:
1. Sudden
events in the natural world. These events may have a very long genesis but
their actual manifestation is dramatically unexpected. Outbreaks of disease are
included in this category, as are illnesses which strike an individual human
unexpectedly. Other examples range from such relatively common events as wind
storms, floods, lightning strikes, blizzards, cold snaps, heat waves, fires,
hail storms, and the like to less common events such as earthquakes, volcanic
eruptions, wild animal attacks, and landslides, to very uncommon and rare
events such as strikes by meteorites or comets. The rarer the event—the greater
the odds against its occurring—the more profound the shock and surprise when it
does happen.
2. Events
which are caused by human volition. We might qualify this by saying
“apparent human volition” because people don’t fully know the reasons for their
actions, in my view. This volition may be a simple decision that carries no
larger purpose (such as what to eat at a given time), it might be something a
human does because of the will of another human (such as the actions of an
employee), it may be something done in the course of ordinary social
interaction, it may be something that a human wishes to do to benefit another
human, or it may be completely malicious in nature. It might have elements of
several of these motives. Most significantly, human volition itself stems from the unique, randomly
expressed variables that make up the consciousness of the individual. No
expression of human volition is identical to any other. This category is
closely related to but does not entirely coincide with…
3. Events
which are caused by human miscalculation or error. This is the source of an
enormous amount of randomness in human life. Human misperception—the false
interpretation, by the relevant portions of the cerebral cortex, of stimuli
coming into the senses—has been the source of countless random errors. People
do not necessarily see what they think they see. They do not necessarily hear
what they think they hear. They miscalculate distances, underestimate times
before a collision, or make other errors of prediction based on misperceived
stimuli. The failure of humans to anticipate negative consequences is a
relative of this misperception. In failure of anticipation, sensory data may be
accurately perceived, but the next step—action based on this perception—is not
consistent with the sensory data received. The role of fatigue and intoxication
in causing human error must also be considered, as well as errors caused by
damage to the brain. The story of human history is so rife with error that no
one can know its full impact. The accidents caused solely by human mistakes, as
opposed to mechanical failures or natural interventions, are quite literally
innumerable. Human mistakes are the great
“wild card” of human history.
4. Events
that occur gradually over long periods of time. These are events that were
not “willed” by anyone, nor are they the product of human incompetence. Neither
are they sudden eruptions of nature. One sub-category of such events is the
physical breakdown of man-made objects, a naturally-caused event less dramatic
than those typical of the first category. Eventually, a machine simply wears
out from the friction involved in its use. Metal becomes brittle. A house needs
repair because of exposure to the elements. Such events, happening over long
periods of time, can cause accidents,
but more often than not such deterioration results in less drastic outcomes.
Another subcategory is the slower processes of nature, such as erosion (caused
by wind, blowing sand, or water), the shifting of tectonic plates, gradual
alterations in the Earth’s climate, slow changes in the Earth’s surface
features, the processes of natural selection that bring about changes in the
genetic composition of a population in a given area, and other such examples.
The sum total of the unpredictable changes brought about by these processes can
be dramatic in the extreme. And a third subcategory is actually the hardest one
to trace: gradual changes in individual humans, or in the attitudes of groups
of humans, or in the interaction of human societies. These kinds of changes,
totally unremarkable in most respects, can still manifest themselves in
profoundly unpredictable and important ways. The cumulative impact on the
direction of this world’s existence brought about by gradual processes is enormous.
5. The action of the truly unpredictable. There are events which are
so utterly unanticipated that they are what Nassim Nicholas Taleb calls Black Swans. Black Swans appear out of
“nowhere” in the sense that most people believed they could not happen and made
no preparation for them. And oftentimes, they are so unprecedented and unusual
that no one could have predicted
them. Taleb presents persuasive evidence that humans tend to grossly
overestimate their control over affairs and their understanding of reality, and
get surprised by Black Swans more often than they would care to admit.5
Arthur C. Clarke characterized
the surprise and disorientation brought about by the discovery of unexpected scientific
principles as failure of imagination—the
(understandable) inability to foresee the radically unpredictable. Examples of
such principles would be those which underlie the existence of x-rays,
radiation, and nuclear energy. No observer, however scientifically sophisticated,
predicted such phenomena would be uncovered because there was no way of doing
so. By their very nature these principles were inconceivable, and their
discovery constituted a highly random set of developments in the sciences.6
6. Events
which involve interrelated and interconnected aspects of all or some of these
sources, acting in unpredictable combination. This is perhaps the most
important category of all. Many, many variables operate simultaneously in
reality. It is beyond human abilities to know all the individual probabilities
of all the variables in a given event. Since the essence of the definition of
randomness is unpredictability, this lack of knowledge is the basis of the
apparently random nature of things, and manifests itself as the perception of randomness. The inability
of humans to comprehend these often blindingly complex combinations limits
their ability to take control of situations, or even to take effective measures
for their own protection. These unpredictable combinations of random events are
also the source of much of the astonishment humans feel as the unexpected plays
out around them.
Many humans are surprised by
unusual events because they overlook what experts in probability refer to as
The Law of Large Numbers. In its essence, it states that if enough repetitions
of a given event occur, then sooner or later every possible outcome will
manifest itself in a statistically predictable way. This was first proved in
1713 by Swiss mathematician James Bernoulli and it has since been confirmed and
its expression made more succinct. Less precisely known as The Law of Averages,
it means that everything that can
happen will happen, given sufficient
opportunity.7 There are many long-shots coming in all the time,
there are many of what I call clusters of probability expressing themselves at
any given moment. In a human population of 7 billion, statistically improbable
things occur every day. They are not
miraculous in nature; they are occurring simply because they had enough chances
to occur.
Humans generally (not
universally) wish to be prepared for unexpected contingencies. In much of human
society, security is defined by the ability to defend one’s self and one’s
loved ones from the effects of randomness. (A friend and former colleague of
mine has said that the human quest for security is largely based on the desire
to find a safe place to sleep.) The acquisition and keeping of weapons is one
of the oldest examples of the desire to be protected from randomness. The much
more recent rise of insurance in the more advanced nations is another example
of this desire. The nature of the complex societies that humans have evolved,
with their governments, law codes, military establishments, and police forces,
can all be seen, in one perspective, as an attempt to increase the
predictability of existence. A whole statistical discipline has arisen based on
the mathematical calculation of risk, a discipline which serves insurers,
gaming interests, and those engaged in finance. For such people, the
calculation of odds is vital to their economic survival.
The attempt to arrange one’s life
in such a way as to avoid chance encounters with disaster is made harder by
poverty, which exposes a human to the effects of bad probabilities to a far greater
extent than those who are more affluent. Impoverished humans live closer both
to the natural elements and to others who are in similar circumstances. They
are exposed, therefore, to a high degree of both natural and human
capriciousness. The social arrangements of a society might therefore be best
understood by the distribution of exposure to randomness within the society’s
population. But even for the most prosperous, the quest for absolute security is a futile one.
Coincidence
Coincidence can be understood as
the simultaneous (or near simultaneous) occurrence, through the action of
probability alone, of two or more events which bear similarities to each other
or which seem to be related.
Coincidences occur because various intersecting chains of unexpected
consequences occasionally produce very similar outcomes at about the same point
in space-time. Because many humans have a poor grasp of probability (and
numbers in general), they tend to see certain events that are merely
coincidental as extraordinary. As John Allen Paulos, a professor of mathematics
has said, a million to one shot comes in hundreds of times every day. Ordinary
examples from human life abound:
--We are thinking of someone and
at the moment we are doing so we get a phone call from that individual or we
meet them on the street.
--We are reading about a
situation in a distant country, and someone within earshot of us happens to
mention that country.
--We happen to be a little short
of the change we need for a purchase and we see a coin of the exact
denomination we need lying unclaimed on the floor of the shop.
--We have a vivid dream about a
disaster occurring, and a disaster very similar to that about which we dreamed
actually occurs.
--We happen to be thinking of an
elderly relative moments before we receive the news that that relative has
died.
--We are playing a dice game. We
perform a small ritual to “guarantee” that a seven will be rolled, and indeed
we roll a seven.
Besides being the products of
simple probability, what do such events have in common? Many people tend to see
in them evidence that the Universe is mysteriously bringing events together
specifically to convey meaning to us. We often hear the expression, “That was
no accident.” Well, in almost every imaginable case, such events are accidents—the accidents of
coincidence. 8
Many people claim—completely
without logic—that events that have no significance, such as odd little
coincidences, are deeply important, in part because these occurrences are so
surprising and so unexpected, and in part because they fail to understand that
causation is statistically explicable. Many people seem to reject the notion
that probability can touch their own
lives. They insist that there must be “good causes” for everything. But just
because a book shelf collapses when we are talking about the possibility of a
book shelf collapsing, it does not mean that our mentioning of the subject
caused it to occur in real life. All of this misinterpretation of coincidences
is a symptom of apophenia, the belief
that events and phenomena that have little or no real significance are
tremendously important. All “omens”, all “prophetic signals”, all “ill winds”,
and all “unlucky signs” are examples of this—and so is the conviction that
coincidences are intrinsically meaningful. Again, ignorance of the Law of Large
Numbers blinds people to the fact that the amazing is actually rather
commonplace.
Some people believe in an alleged
phenomenon called synchronicity, which was conceived by the psychoanalyst Carl
Jung. From The Skeptic’s Dictionary:
His notion of synchronicity is that there is an acausal
principle that links events having a similar meaning by their coincidence in
time rather than sequentially. He claimed that there is a synchrony between the
mind and the phenomenal world of perception.9
Furthermore, Jung felt himself
capable of “interpreting” these “meaningful coincidences” through sheer
intuition. There is no empirical evidence for any of this at all. In fact, Jung
believed many bizarre things, and may have been afflicted with mental illness
himself.
Why do people want to believe in
the significance of coincidences? Why do they focus on the seeming “success”
of systems designed to “beat the odds”?
Why do they fall for scams based on human ignorance of probability? Paulos
explains that many humans have a sort of mental filtering mechanism that
emphasizes successes and passes over defeats. We remember the time we hit it
big on a bet; we forget all the losses we incurred before and after it. In a similar
fashion, humans remember all the “hits” of coincidence, forgetting all the
thousands and thousands of times such seemingly extraordinary events did not occur.10
Is the world explicable by
algorithmic means, or is reality essentially non-algorithmic? In many cases, we
can know outcomes in the aggregate; we cannot know them in the particular, much
as we can know the behavior of subatomic particles as a group but not the
behavior of individual ones. But subatomic particles are much more predictable
than the bearers of consciousness, for whom a number of behavioral options are
open. It is the evolution of consciousness that in many ways has added a new
layer of uncertainty to reality. The bearers of consciousness are affected by
the apparent randomness in which they find themselves, but they contribute to
this randomness by their very nature. They are much less in control of their
lives than they would like to admit, and the hidden realities of randomness and
probability dog them at every turn. But in crucial ways, the most dangerous
aspects of this randomness come from their fellow humans, the actions of whom
over the centuries have helped create the very uncertainties that humans most
fear. Humans have helped unleash sequences of events that have played themselves
out in wildly unpredictable ways across both space and time. It is to these
sequences that we now turn in order to further understand the unseen realities
in which we are immersed—and against which we so often struggle in vain.
1. Mlodinow, Leonard, The Drunkard’s Walk: How Randomness Rules Our Lives, p. 23
2. Mlodinow, pp. 33-34
3. Mlodinow, p. 35
4. Ash, Robert, Basic Probability Theory, passim
5. Taleb, Nassim Nicholas, The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable, passim
6. Clarke, Arthur C., Profiles of the Future, pp. 12-21
7. Grinstead, Charles M. and Snell, J. Laurie, Introduction to Probability, 2nd edition,
pp. 305-312
8. Paulos, John Allen, Innumeracy: Mathematical Illiteracy and Its Consequences, pp.
25-48
9. “Synchronicity”, Skeptic’s Dictionary,
located at: http://www.skepdic.com/jung.html
10. Paulos, pp. 33-34
No comments:
Post a Comment